In classical philosophy the discipline of metaphysics was a very popular way to try to understand the universe and our place in it. Literally meaning “after physics,” the word comes from the untitled section of Aristotle’s work that follows the section entitled “physics,” hence ‘metaphysics’. Metaphysics, as the word is used in philosophy, refers to an attempt to formulate a comprehensive, all-inclusive theory of reality, defining and describing its nature. Prior to the development of the scientific method, this included “natural philosophy” (the old name for science) as a sub-section. The primary method for creating a ‘metaphysic’ is inductive reasoning – drawing general conclusions about the world from a finite amount of experiences. Wikipedia gives us a great example of an inductive reasoning: Every life form we know of depends on water to live (an observation.) Therefore, every life form depends on water to live (an inductive conclusion). Clearly the second is not necessarily true based on the observation, although based on what we know, we might assume that this will hold true, even on other planets. But that’s an assumption, not a fact. We can call induction, and thereby metaphysics itself, nothing more than an ‘educated guess’.
The problem with induction, and metaphysics as a whole, is that it relies on pure reason to take a stab in the dark about unobserved phenomena. If we accept a particular metaphysic and its inductive reasoning, we tend to limit our thinking. For instance, if we reason that, based on observed life (life on earth) needing water to live, all life, including that on other planets, needs water to live, then we think of potential life in a limited (although reasonable) way. When looking for life on other planets, we look for water first. That may or may not work out for us, but if life forms exist somewhere out there that do not require water, we are less likely to find them.
We use induction constantly. We assume that because gravity has held true for all of known history, it will continue tomorrow, although there’s actually no certainty of that (no empirical observation). We assume that, based on the fact that we are alive today, we will be alive tomorrow, although there’s clearly no guarantee. Metaphysicians of the past have used induction to ‘prove’ the existence of God (Spinoza), a Platonic world of ideas, and the division of nature into mind and matter (Descartes), but thanks to the advent of empiricism and the scientific method, modern philosophy regards their conclusions as suspect.
Turning back to religion, we find that their founders had certain religious experiences that we can equate with observation in science. A certain uncommon thing (something different than average day-to-day experience) was experienced by a person, and this person tried to make sense of it. In other words, the religious founder had an uncommon experience which impacted his current understanding of the world in one way or another, and in order to create a new worldview incorporating the new information, created a sort of metaphysical theory by inductive reasoning. I know, I’m being extremely vague and general, but only because I want to include all major religions. Each founder reacted differently, may have experienced differently, and certainly induced different conclusions. Lets use the Rishis as an example: Consciously searching after truth beyond the appearance of the world (based on what they heard from others), they used various methods (yoga, hallucinogens, etc) to bring about certain experiences. They described these experiences as Indra, Brahman, Shiva, etc. From this basis, they induced a metaphysical corpus which includes everything from moral law, social law, physical theories, even medical theories. As each of these seers described things in different ways, their accounts were later organized by others into 4 Vedas, which were then connected to later commentaries and inductive speculation (the Upanishads), integrated with fictional epics (Ramayana, Bhagavad Gita), and refined by a commentarial tradition into Vedanta (meaning literally “The end, or conclusions, of the Vedas”). Over thousands of years we come to a rich body of religious and cultural information we call Hinduism.
While we may look at this rich tradition and admire its complexity and beauty, we cannot ignore the problems. The inductive reasoning that postulated that different types of people should follow laws appropriate to their role in society (dharma) became crystallized into the unfortunate caste system of the India. Further, the deep cultural respect for tradition discouraged any attempt to look beyond what is in the scriptures (like only looking for life on water-rich planets), creating a setting in which thousands of years of guess-work based on limited spiritual experience defines one’s world view. Intellectual life for a long time in India included logical debates which were less about reality or truth than about the clever ability to manipulate the massive scriptural corpus to prove one’s point. My guess is based upon your guess, like a castle on a cloud.
The same certainly holds true for Christianity. After the initial spate of religious experience among Christ and the Disciples, quite a few Gospels turned up around the ancient world. Eventually the four we know became canon, around the time of St. Augustine (4th century). Many Gospels were rejected to make room for those four, most because they were either suspect in authenticity, or they conflicted with the metaphysics of those with the most influence. The “Church Doctors” then put together their metaphysics based on the canon (and really, the New Testament doesn’t give us a lot of actual information about the world), and this became the Christian tradition. The dogmas of a church are really just metaphysics, but regarded as infallible by tradition. Heresy is really just when one person’s inductive reasoning conflicts with the standard metaphysic.
For this reason, empiricists tend to regard metaphysics and religion both as a waste of time, even calling religious or metaphysical statements “meaningless”. David Hume wrote of classical metaphysics:
“When we run over libraries, persuaded of these principles [Hume’s empirical principals], what havoc must we make? If we take in our hand any volume; of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames: for it can contain nothing by sophistry and illusion.” – Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding.
When we also consider the difficulties of knowledge and perception, we become even more skeptical that such grandiose conclusions, such as offered by metaphysicians and theologians, can ever attain to real knowledge. Consider further the fact that if the speculations of metaphysically inclined ‘natural philosophers’ could be so wrong in their conclusions about the physical world that everyone can touch and see without any special effort, then what is the likelihood of any metaphysic being accurate in describing the nature of what is not seen by all? I’d say it’s not bloody likely.
While most empiricists call for rejecting religion as a whole on these grounds, this seems to me a bit hasty. As top-heavy as religious doctrine becomes, it is still based on human experience. People have spiritual experiences all the time, to varying degrees of intensity, and I myself have had quite a few. As skeptical as I am about most theology, I cannot doubt what I have experienced, just as you don’t doubt that the earth exists under your feet. We also cannot doubt that unlike a perception of political rights, the scientific method, or written language, religion is a truly universal cultural phenomena. Religious experience, in its primary sense, is universal to humanity, in the same way as spoken language, an upright walk, and music exist wherever there is man. For a modern atheist to proclaim that there is no God is bad inductive reasoning. He makes a negative observation: “I have never experienced God” and by inductive reasoning concludes “there is no God.” By that same logic we might go from “I have never seen Transformers 2” and therefore “Transformers 2 doesn’t exist.” As much as I wish that were the case, just because I lack experience of it, does not make it not exist. Mr. Atheist might then say “but Dave, you can read reviews of Transformers 2, hear about it from others, and even go rent it yourself and watch it. You can verify its existence, but you can’t do that with God.” To which I must respond that there are no shortage of churches out there who profess God’s existence, you can hear about him from people who’ll even come knock on your door to chat, and according to the mystics (like the yogis), you can even train yourself to eventually experience God. While that might take years, it also takes quite a bit of training to personally verify most scientific claims. Most atheists, secure in their own inductive reasoning, are unwilling to make the sacrifices necessary to even attempt having a religious experience. We might liken this to the fact that, despite the efforts of those who might insist on its existence, I’m unwilling to sacrifice my time, intelligence or sanity to verify the existence of Transformers 2 by actually watching it.
Cont. in Part III
"The problem with induction, and metaphysics as a whole, is that it relies on pure reason." Reason is how we go from the known to the unknown. By saying this is a problem, are you implying that there is some other way to go from the known to the unknown?
ReplyDeleteAlso, the inductive fallacy is not the only one at work here. Descartes made logical errors besides that when he "proved" that God exists.
Empiricism does not overthrow logic. You make it sound like empiricists found counterexamples that refuted Descartes conclusions. It's not that simple. If the observations of scientists did not fit within a logical framework, they would not have caused a scientific revolution. Kuhn (1962) called this a paradigm shift.
And that gets us to the major difference between God and Transformers 2. Transformers 2 fits within a logical framework, or paradigm, that forms the basis of our experience. It is easy to believe in the existence of Transformers 2 because it is a movie which is like many other movies which I know to exist according my experience and what I can induce from that experience. Trying to convince the mythical bushman of the existence of Transformers 2 might be considerably more difficult.
I say "mythical bushman" because the real bushmen know all about modern society. In fact, it is very difficult to find a culture that has not been exposed to TV and the radio these days. And the reason for that is that the scientific paradigm that allows for TV and the radio is not arbitrary. Unlike the metaphysics of Plato which reasoned from the seen to the unseen and left us with castles on clouds, quantum mechanics is able to give very accurate description of something that cannot be seen by anyone. Quantum mechanics allows for radio and many other strange things.
One thing that it does not allow is an interventionist God. For the record, it says nothing about what happened before the big bang. There is nothing incompatible between deism and science. But there is something incompatible between theism and science where by "theism" I mean belief in an interventionist God.
Yes, atheists will grant that induction cannot completely rule out the possibility of God any more than it can completely rule out the possibility of "a china teapot revolving about the sun in an elliptical orbit" between the Earth and Mars (Russell, 1952).
That's what I get for trying to lighten things up. Ok, Transformers 2 is a bad example (and one infers from everything else Michael Bey has created, a bad movie), but you bring up a good point with your "Mythical Bushman."
ReplyDeleteJust like the Bushman is a myth because just about everyone has at least some reference to movies, TV, etc, bushman or no, the truth is that most people also have some degree of experience of mystic states, however mild, because so many of them seem to come through the emotions. While many of the organized religions are falling out of favor, even still, the 'religious impulse' isn't going away. There are, however, some people who have very little feeling for this, and for some reason, I tend to give them a bigger piece of the population pie than most surveys have shown. These are folks like Christopher Hitchens (who I will write about in my next post), who seem unable to do other than take religious belief literally. These "hard minded" folks are surely good at some things, just like others may be more suited to the arts (I would guess that they are not the later).
I was reading William James today and came across this which reminds me of my point:
"Few of us are not in some way infirm, or even diseased; and our very infirmities help us unexpectedly. In the psychopathic temperament we have the emotionality which is the sine qua non of moral perception; we have the intensity and tendency to emphasis which are the essence of practical moral vigor; and we have the love of metaphysics and mysticism which carry one's interests beyond the surface of the sensible world. What, then, is more natural than that this temperament should introduce one to regions of religious truth, to corners of the universe, which your robust Philistine type of nervous system, forever offering its biceps to be felt, thumping its breast, and thanking heaven that it hasn't a single morbid fiber in its composition, would be sure to hide forever from its self-satisfied possessors?"
And yeah, I went overboard on my criticism of metaphysics from a empiricist point of view. Reading too much warps the mind. :)